Category The Enigma of. the Aerofoil

A Conclusion and a Warning

My question at the beginning of this volume was: Why did British experts in aerodynamics resist the circulatory theory of lift when their German coun­terparts embraced it and developed it into a useful and predictive theory? My answer has been: Because the British placed aerodynamics in the hands of mathematical physicists while the Germans placed it in the hands of math­ematically sophisticated engineers. More specifically, my answer points to a divergence between the culture of mathematical physics developed out of the Cambridge Tripos tradition and the culture of technical mechanics devel­oped in the German technical colleges.

This abbreviated version of my argument and my conclusion is correct, but a condensed formulation of this kind carries with it certain dangers. It may invite, and may seem to permit, assimilation into a familiar, broader narrative, which destroys its real significance. Thus it may appear that the “moral” of the story is that (at least for a time) certain social prejudices en­couraged resistance to a novel scientific theory and led to scientific evidence being ignored or overridden by social interests and cultural inertia. Accord­ing to this stereotype the story came to an end when “rational factors” or “epistemic factors” eventually overcame “social factors” and science was able to continue on its way—a little sadder and wiser, perhaps, but still securely on the path of progress.

Is there really any danger of the episode that I have described in so much detail being trivialized in this way? I fear there is.100 In one form or another, the narrative framework I have just sketched is widely accepted. It has nu­merous defenders in the academic world who confidently recommend it for its alleged realism and rectitude. It is deemed realistic because no one who adopts this view need deny that science is a complicated business. Scientists are, after all, human. Sometimes the personality or the metaphysical beliefs of a scientist may imprint themselves on a historical episode. Sometimes politi­cal interests and ideologies will intervene to complicate the development of a subject and perhaps even distort and corrupt a line of scientific inquiry. What worldly person would ever want to deny that this can happen? But who could approve of these things or, after sober reflection, think that they represent the full story of scientific progress? The intrusions of extra-scientific interests must therefore be exposed as deviations from an ideal that is characteristic of science at its rational, impersonal, and objective best. As well as personal and social contingencies (the argument goes on), it is vital to acknowledge that there are rational principles that, ultimately, stand outside the historical process and outside society. These represent the normative standards that sci­ence must embody if it is to achieve its goal. Fortunately the norms of rational thinking are realized with sufficient frequency that science manages to do its proper job. The norms ensure that the Voice of Reason and the Voice of Nature are heard. With due effort, and a degree of good fortune, this is how science actually works. The rest (the deviations and failings) merely provide a human-interest story of which, perhaps, too much has been made.101

Doesn’t the episode I have described fit into this stereotype? The dispute over the circulation theory ended because the evidence had become too strong to resist. Isn’t that really all there was to it? The British experts were initially too impressed by the great name of Rayleigh, and their resistance to the circulation theory was not a credit to their rationality. Eventually, though none too soon, they came round. Ultimately, therefore, evidence and reason triumphed over prejudice, tradition, and inertia. Reality stubbornly thwarted vested interests, and rationality subverted conventional habits and complacent expectations. Knowledge triumphed over Society. Isn’t this how my story ends?

The answer is no. This is not the story, and it is not how the story ends. Such a framework does not do justice to even half of the story I have told. In reality the end of the story is of a piece with its beginning and its middle. There was continuity both in the particular parameters of the episode I have described as well as in the general epistemological principles that ran through it. The supporters of the circulation theory never provided an adequate ac­count of the origin of circulation, and the critics never deduced the aero­dynamics of a wing from Stokes’ equations. Nor were there any qualitative differences in the relations linking knowledge to society and to the mate­rial world at the end of the story compared with the beginning of the story. There were changes of many kinds throughout the course of the episode, but they were not changes in the fundamentals of cognition or the modes of its expression. Fundamental social processes were operating in the same, principled way before, during, and after the episode described, and they are operating in the same way today. Society was not an intruder that was even­tually dispelled or an alien force that had to be subordinated to the norms of rationality or the voice of nature. There was no Manichean struggle between the Social and the Rational.

Trivializing versions of how the story ends may appeal to propagandists who want to spin simple moral tales, but to the historian and sociologist such tales indicate that the complexities of the episode are being edited out and its structure distorted. This danger is amplified if only a summary version of the story is retained in the memory. To offset this tendency I want to make explicit the methodological framework in which the story should be located, and I want to defend this framework against trivializing objections and mis­guided alternatives. Such is the function of the discussions in the final chap­ter. The aim is to keep the details of the story alive and its structure intact while, at the same time, reflecting on its broader significance.102

The Equation of Continuity (and Some Conventions)

The equations of motion for an ideal fluid were derived from two basic state­ments. In a sense, said Cowley and Levy, “these two statements and all that they involve are a definition of the nature of the fluid.” Furthermore, “all de­ductions regarding its behavior can only be a recasting of these [statements] into a new but equivalent form” (37). The two statements were as follows:

(1) The mass of fluid in any region remains constant. This is called the condi­tion of “continuity.” And (2) the motion of every fluid element is consistent with Newton’s Laws of Motion. To spell out the first of these principles, con­sider a small volume through which the fluid flows. This is represented in cross section in figure 2.1 by the rectangle ABCD, with sides labeled dx and dy. Before going further I should say something about the conventions used in such diagrams in hydrodynamics. The d and 8 (delta) symbols indicate that the lengths are not just “small” in a commonsense manner of speaking but have been, or will be, made “infinitely small” in the course of the mathemati­cal reasoning. They will be subject to a “limiting process” in which it is as­sumed that they can be made ever smaller without the shrinkage demand­ing any significant changes in the pattern of reasoning (which is essentially what Lamb meant in the passage quoted at the head of the chapter). The reason why the volume can be represented by an area is because the volume is assumed to be of unit depth, so the number 1, representing the depth, is present but can be suppressed. Diagrams of this kind thus amount to a two­dimensional cross section of the flow, and the situation portrayed is routinely referred to as a two-dimensional flow.14

Two-dimensional flow diagrams do not allow any representation of what happens at the edges of the figure other than those shown in the cross section. The parts of the object that go into, and out of, the page are not shown. In describing a situation in this truncated way, the mathematician assumes that nothing significant happens at the edges that are not represented. In reality this is not true, so all discussions of two-dimensional flow are by their na­ture simplifications. These simplifications will become especially significant when the object under discussion is a wing and the cross section takes on the shape of an aerofoil. In the literature on aerodynamics the simplified, two-dimensional diagram of the flow is then often called a diagram of the flow around an “infinite” wing. This usage can be disconcerting, but it is simply a way of saying that the flow shown in the picture is representative of what goes on in the central parts of the wing. The wingtips are assumed to be

The Equation of Continuity (and Some Conventions)

figure 2.i. Small control volume used to arrive at the equation of continuity. Fluid flowing into the volume equals fluid flowing out. From Cowley and Levy 1918, 37.

sufficiently far from the action that they do not interfere in any way and can be ignored. The literature on hydrodynamics and aerodynamics is full of ref­erences to infinity. The word “infinity” can nearly always be read as meaning either “so far away that it causes no disturbance” or “so far away that it can be considered to be undisturbed.”

Having dealt with these terminological matters, I now come back to the small volume represented in figure 2.1.15 The fluid is assumed to be incom­pressible with constant density p, so in a given time interval the mass of fluid flowing into the volume always equals the mass flowing out. In the x-direction the speed of flow into the volume is designated by u and the speed of outflow by ^u+d~^x j. The symbol du/dx means “the rate of change of u with x,” so the expression in parentheses refers to the original speed plus the change of speed. The change can be positive or negative. The mass entering the control volume per unit time is puby and the mass leaving is pi u+—Sx | Sy. The

I dx j

same procedure is repeated for the flow in the y-direction. In each case the quantity of fluid entering and leaving the control volume is obtained by mul­tiplying the speeds by the density of the fluid and dimensions of the face crossed by the flow. Mathematically, the condition of continuity is then ex­pressed by summing all these quantities and equating the sum to zero. Fluid in must equal fluid out, with zero shortfall. When the expression for this zero sum is simplified, the equation that results takes the form

du + dv 0 dx dy

This expression states, in a mathematical form, the condition of continuity.

The Empirical Study of Rayleigh Flow

Reports and Memoranda No. 16, of September 1909, was a note prepared by Mallock on experiments that involved moving flat and curved plates through a tank of water and measuring the forces on them.24 The plates were rect­angles whose sides were in the ratios of 2:1, 1:1, and 1:2 and were inclined at various angles between 0° and 90° to the direction of motion. Measurements were taken at various speeds between 150 and 500 feet per minute. The plates were attached to scales in order to read off the forces exerted on them. The resultant force on the plate was broken down into a resistance force (the drag directly opposing the motion) and a lateral force at right angles to the direc­tion of travel (a lift force). A graph of the results showed that the measure­ments “differ greatly from the values calculated on the assumption that the pressure on the rear surface is uniform and equal to that of the fluid at a dis­tance” (40), that is, calculated on the assumption that there was “dead water” behind the plate. Mallock’s explanation for the disparity was the same as Ray­leigh’s.25 There can, said Mallock, “be no doubt that the distribution of the pressure over the rear surface and its difference from the pressure prevailing in the fluid at a distance, account both for the peculiarities of the resistance and the lateral thrust curves” (40).

There was a negative pressure at the back of the plate, and Mallock sug­gested that the cause of this suction effect was eddy formation: “The fact of negative pressure being found on the down-stream side of the surface is ul­timately connected with the formation of eddies. . . nor will a satisfactory explanation of such features. . . be obtained until the formation of eddies under varying conditions has been investigated” (40). These ideas had al­ready found expression in one of the very first Reports and Memoranda, that of May 19, 1909, titled “Memorandum on General Questions to Be Studied.” Much of this publication was devoted to the results of several series of experi­ments Mallock had performed on plates in currents of air.26 He described the general form of the curves relating angle of incidence to lift and drag. The lift increases in a roughly linear fashion but only up to a certain, critical angle. After this it declines more or less sharply. In the region of the critical angle, he noted, the airflow had an unsteady, oscillating character accompanied by the formation of eddies.

Mallock went on to make the following significant remark about the dif­ference between perfect fluids and real fluids: “The details of eddy formation are also important. The eddy in a real fluid differs greatly from the ideal vor­tex ring. The latter is a separate entity which could not be made, and, if exist­ing, could not be destroyed. The eddies in real fluids are composite structures in which layers of originally different velocities are wound up together” (22). Mallock was arguing that the turbulence that characterizes real flows can­not be modeled by the kind of vortices that can exist in a perfect fluid. He was implicitly citing one of the most important results of classical hydrody­namics. Kelvin had provided a rigorous proof of a result that had long been known in one form or another, namely, that vortex or rotational motion in an ideal fluid can be neither created nor destroyed. The governing equations of ideal flow did not allow a vortex to be generated (for example, by the mo­tion of a solid body immersed within the fluid), nor could any existing vortex be damped down or dissipated. Mallock concluded that an adequate under­standing of the flow of a real fluid (such as air), around a real object (such as a wing), cannot be achieved using a theory of an ideal, perfectly inviscid, fluid. Like Rayleigh, he now believed it was necessary to take account of viscosity.

A further criticism of Kirchhoff-Rayleigh flow was contained in Reports and Memoranda No. 24, dated April 21, 1910. This was written by T. E. Stan­ton, the head of the Engineering Department at the NPL, and his assistant Leonard Bairstow.27 The aim of the research was to discover the relative ef­ficiency of the various rudders and lifting surfaces that were used on airships. Could these be modeled as flat planes set at an angle to the flow, and could Rayleigh’s formula be used to predict the forces on them? Recall that Rayleigh had deduced the formula for the distance of the center of pressure of the resultant aerodynamic force from the leading edge of the plate. Stanton and Bairstow carried out measurements in the air channel to test this. They found that “the experimentally determined position of the centre of pressure for the pattern of rudders used are in all cases ahead of the theoretical position for a thin plate” (75). Here was a second blow to the utility of Kirchhoff-Rayleigh flow. First it underestimated the force on wing; now it emerged that it located that force in the wrong place.

The next step was to try to render the flow around wings and plates vis­ible and to capture them in photographs. The photographs were provided for the Advisory Committee in 1912 by C. G. Eden in Reports and Memoranda No. 58.28 Eden injected a mixture of aniline and toluene into the flow of water in a small water channel, a 3 X 4-inch cross section, containing a small, 1-inch­wide model wing that could be given various angles of incidence. The flow had a speed of 1 inch per second and could be illuminated by means of an arc lamp. The specific gravity of the injected fluid was adjusted to match that of the water so that it did not alter the character of the flow. The optical proper­ties of the oil were such that at an angle of about 70° to the incident beam, the oil drops appeared as bright dots and could be photographed. Commenting on the resulting photographs, Eden described the effect of putting the wing at different angles of incidence, saying, “At small angles up to 9° no eddies are formed, but it will be seen that between 9° and 10° a change takes place, and at 10° there is a small ‘dead water’ region at the back of the plate and the eddying of the flow in the wake is clearly shown” (99). At first it may seem that the photographs were evidence in favor of Kirchhoff-Rayleigh flow. Eden detected eddies that the theory could not explain, but he reported a clearly visible region of “dead water,” which is the most characteristic feature of the flow. The real significance of the photographs, however, came out when they were related to model wings as they were being studied in the wind channel.

Bairstow and Melvill Jones produced two papers in 1912 that had a direct bearing on the meaning of the photographs. The first, Reports and Mem­oranda No. 53, was a general assessment of the properties of aerofoils, “as deduced from the results of various aeronautical laboratories.”29 These in-

The Empirical Study of Rayleigh Flow

figure 3.6. The typical relation between the lift and the angle of incidence of a wing. The lift increases in a linear way with increased angle of incidence up to a critical angle, at which the lift begins to decline rapidly. At this angle the wing “stalls.” Notice that a typical wing still generates some lift for small negative angles of incidence, that is, when sloping down.

cluded Eiffel’s near Paris and Prandtl’s in Gottingen. These results, said Bair – stow and Jones, made it possible to identify the salient features of aircraft wings, both qualitatively and quantitatively. Suppose a wing is aligned with the general direction of airflow. It generates a lift force at right angles to the direction of flow, and as the angle of incidence is slowly increased the lift increases in an approximately linear manner. At a certain point, around 10° to 15°, the lift reaches a maximum and then declines, sometimes very sharply. This was Mallock’s “critical” angle. Finally, because the wing produces lift when it is horizontal, the position of zero lift must occur when the wing has a slight negative angle of incidence. The general form of the graph relating lift to incidence, as described by Bairstow and Melvill Jones, is indicated in figure 3.6.

In their next report, “Experiments on Models of Aeroplane Wings,” of March 1912, Bairstow and Melvill Jones made two important moves.30 First, they reinforced the evidence that the factors regulating the amount of lift in a wing are precisely those that are excluded by the discontinuity theory, namely, the shape of the upper surface. Second, they made the crucial link to Eden’s photographs. To show the significance of the upper surface, they used a series of aerofoil sections with a flat base but (1) varied the camber of the upper surface and then (2) altered the position along the chord of the maximum ordinate. (The camber was measured by the ratio of the maximum height of the curved upper surface to the chord.) They demonstrated how changes in camber altered the ratio of the lift to the drag. Thus, starting from a nearly flat wing, an increase in camber at first increased and then decreased this ratio, the maximum being for a wing with a curvature of 0.05. The op­timum position of the highest point in the upper surface turned out to be one-third of the chord from the leading edge. Variation of the curvature of the lower surface of the wing, by contrast, produced little effect on the lift or drag. Thus the systematic accumulation of inductive evidence about the be­havior of wings consolidated Rayleigh’s early doubts about his classic results. The most significant aerodynamic processes on a wing had, on his analysis, been located on the wrong surface.

Eden’s photographs showed a winglike shape at various angles below and above the critical angle. At small angles there were no eddies, so the flow was smooth and stayed close to the surface of the plate or wing. Around 9°, eddies formed behind the plate and the smooth flow broke down. Here the illuminated oil drops stayed as spots of light and did not show up as lines because they did not move during the exposure time. As Bairstow and Melvill Jones put it, “It seems clear that the alterations in pressure at the critical angle are due to the sudden breakdown in the character of the fluid flow in the neighbourhood of this angle, and in this connection the photographs . . . are of interest. . . . It will be noted that above the critical angle the fluid near the upper surface is practically ‘dead’” (10).

The implication was that dead air does indeed form behind a wing, as in Rayleigh flow—but only after the wing has passed the critical angle. Bairstow, Melvill Jones, and Eden were all aware that this reasoning had a weakness. The experiment was in water while the conclusion was about air. The conditions of similarity, required for a confident inference from the one phenomenon to the other, were not strictly satisfied.31 The fact remained that the photographs that looked most like Kirchhoff-Rayleigh flow showed a wing that was over the critical angle.32 This information pointed to an important but disconcert­ing conclusion. The mathematical studies devoted to Kirchhoff-Rayleigh flow were not describing at all how a wing can be so effective in producing lift. In as far as this model of flow over a wing approximated to reality, it was actually describing the breakdown of the pattern that was required for the efficient working of a wing. If they described anything, the formulas of Kirchhoff – Rayleigh flow were the mathematics of a stall, when lift fails. They described the situation when an aircraft was about to fall out of the sky.33

The Balanced-Flap Anomaly

As well as the empirical support briefly mentioned by O’Gorman, some fur­ther evidence favorable to Lanchester emerged in the following year. It came from Bairstow’s own laboratory and arose from the attempt to clarify some disconcerting experimental results about control surfaces. With the con­struction of ever-larger aircraft, the forces that pilots had to exert on the con­trols became correspondingly greater. To overcome this problem the controls were “balanced,” that is, part of the area of the control surface was positioned in front of the hinge around which it turned so that some of the aerodynamic forces worked with, rather than against, the pilot. An experimental study of balanced controls was carried out at the National Physical Laboratory in early 1916 by John Robert Pannell and Norman Robert Campbell. Pannell, who had been on the staff since 1906, was the senior assistant in the Aerodynamics Department. He was a familiar figure who bicycled to work every morning, arriving on wet days with an umbrella held aloft in one hand while steering with the other. His main concern was with tests on full-size airship, and he was to die in 1921 when the R38 met with disaster on its trial flight.68 The balancing experiments, however, were conducted using the “flaps” on an air­craft wing. “Flap” was the old name for the lateral control surfaces, today called ailerons, which allow the pilot to bank and roll the aircraft.

Pannell’s co-worker in these experiments was a Cambridge experimental physicist who had played a prominent role in early debates about relativity theory.69 Campbell, who had been seconded to the NPL for war work, was in the process of writing a book on scientific method, Physics: The Elements, which was published after the war and was to prove an influential work in the philosophy of science. Campbell argued for the importance of models in scientific inference and theory construction.70 On this occasion the models that interested Campbell were not models of the atom or the electromagnetic field but scale models of the wings of a 110-foot-span biplane that was under construction at the Royal Aircraft Factory.71

The “flaps” of the projected aircraft ran along the rear edge of the outer portion of the wings but also included the tips of the wings themselves. When the part of the control surface that was on the trailing edge was lowered, then the part of the wingtip that was connected to it, and that was in front of the axel on which it pivoted, went up. The whole tip of the wing was thus part of the flap. This construction was meant to give the desired balance. Pannell and

Campbell wanted to find the proportion of the area that should be in front of the axel. The model wings were placed vertically in the 4 X 4-foot tunnel at a wind speed of 40 feet per second. Different proportions of fore and aft area were tested with the wings set at 0°, +4°, and +12° to the wind and with the flaps (and tips) put at a variety of angles relative to the main wings.

It proved impossible to find a fully satisfactory balance. Frustratingly, there was no ratio of the areas, fore and aft of the pivot, that fully balanced over the desired range of angles. Also, when looked at in detail, the results had some odd features. On occasion, where the experimenters had expected to be able to detect forces at work on the wingtip, there weren’t any: “In particular it was found that when the main planes of a biplane were inclined at +12° to the wind, there was no moment on the portion of the wing flap forward of the hinge, if this flap was inclined at an angle of -5° to the wind.”72 This result suggested that the flow of air near the wingtip was itself at a negative angle to the undisturbed flow. Given the conventions for designating angles positive or negative, this meant that the air near the wingtip was moving upward rela­tive to the wing. The air was going round the tips from what, during normal flight, would count as the lower to the upper surface.

In order to shed light on this, Pannell and Campbell conducted a further, qualitative investigation of the flow near the tips.73 Using a direction and ve­locity meter to plot the velocity components of the moving air, they found what they called “a very simple and obvious explanation” for their “remark­able results.” It became clear that air was indeed flowing round the wingtips from the lower to the upper surface. This was associated with a movement of air along the span of the wing, that is, not just from the leading to the trailing edge of the wing but lengthwise along it. There was a component of outward movement, toward the tips, on the lower surface and an inward movement, away from the tips, on the upper surface. Pannell and Campbell argued that

The presence of this flow round the wing tips affords, in outline at least, an explanation of the result on the balancing of wing flaps. . . . For, if there is a marked flow near the wing tip directed from the lower to the upper surface, a plane parallel to this flow will experience no wind force. Now it was precisely when the balancing flap was inclined at a negative angle to the wind, so that its plane lay along a flow having a component from the under to the upper side of the plane, that the experiments indicated that there was no force on it. (141)

The qualitative study also addressed the component of flow along the chord of the wing, that is, in the direction of flight rather than around the tips or along the span. Measurements were taken with the direction and ve­locity meter to build up a picture of the disturbed flow. Next, the steady, undisturbed flow was subtracted from it. If the resultant flow was made up of two parts, the free stream plus a circulation, this subtraction would expose the circulatory component. This is exactly what it did. In the experimenter’s words, it emerged that “the component of the wind disturbance which is par­allel to the direction of flight is in the direction of flight almost everywhere below the wing, and in the opposite direction everywhere above the wing. There is therefore some indication of the cyclical motion of the air round the wing in the vertical plane of flight which has been assumed by Mr. Lanchester in his discussion of the theory of the aerofoil” (142). Although the full path of the circulation had not been traced, those parts of it above and below the wing had been factored out and, as it were, exposed to view. Here again was evidence for the reality of the circulatory component that was central to Lanchester’s theory.

Kutta’s 1910 Paper

Unlike the 1902 report of his work, Kutta’s 1910 paper was long and detailed. It was called “Uber eine mit den Grundlagen des Flugproblems in Beziehung stehende zweidimensionale Stromung” (On a two-dimensional flow relevant to the fundamental problem of flight).27 All the basic reasoning in the paper and much of the detailed working were made explicit. It covered some fifty pages of the proceedings of the Royal Bavarian Academy of Science and in­volved mathematical techniques that ranged from the general and abstract to the concrete and numerical.28 Using Kutta’s own headings, I shall go over the seven sections of the paper to convey the structure of the argument.

Klein and the General-Staff Officers

Prandtl wrote his paper on the boundary layer while holding the chair of mechanics at the technische Hochschule in Hanover. Felix Klein (fig. 7.3) soon arranged for him to be called to Gottingen. In subsequent years Klein contin­ued to use his contacts with powerful government ministers, such as Friedrich Althoff, to support Prandtl and his work. Although his greatest mathematical achievements were now behind him, it was during the period 1890 -1914 that Klein was at the height of his influence as an academic politician.19 The in­stitutional structures created in Gottingen by Klein provided the context for Prandtl’s aeronautical work. It is hardly surprising that Klein always remained a figure whom Prandtl revered.20

In the years from the turn of the century and through the period of the

Klein and the General-Staff Officers

figure 7.3. Felix Klein (1849-1925). Klein, one of the greatest mathematicians of his time, has been called a “countermodernist,” but he was a tireless academic reformer and the mentor of Ludwig Prandtl. Klein brought Prandtl to Gottingen and encouraged his aerodynamic research. (By permission of the Niedersachsische Staats – und Universitatsbibliothek Gottingen)

Weimar Republic, Gottingen was a place of extraordinary intellectual bril­liance in the fields of mathematics and physics. The university was the home of not only Felix Klein but David Hilbert, Hermann Minkowsky, and Her­mann Weyl. They all played leading roles in the sometimes tense discussions that took place over the mathematical foundations of general relativity and the geometrical nature of space, time, and matter. It is right that these aspects of the Gottingen scene have attracted the attention of historians of science and have been subject to detailed analysis.21 Nevertheless, for my purposes it is important to ensure that this aspect of Gottingen does not dazzle us. It must not obscure the very different character of the work done by Prandtl and his school.

The two greatest Gottingen mathematicians of that time, Klein and Hil­bert, represented divergent intellectual tendencies. Hilbert’s work can be seen as formal and abstract, whereas Klein’s was more concrete and intui­tive. Hilbert has been described as a “modernist,” while Klein has been pre­sented as a “countermodernist.”22 The differences between the work of the two men are a matter of continuing discussion among historians of math­ematics. The sharpness of the contrast between them has, perhaps, been blunted by recent scholarship, and the degree of overlap in their interests is now better appreciated.23 Despite this, something of the older polarity still remains. Both men wanted to increase unity in the field of mathematics, but they sought unity in different ways and aspired to a qualitatively dif­ferent kind of unity. Hilbert looked for unity through powerful methods and results that would radically reconfigure what had gone before. Klein sought unity through an encyclopedic and cumulative arrangement of re­sults. He was opposed to the bitter sectarianism of the competing “schools” of mathematicians in the German universities and sought to cure it not by the victory of one tendency, but by an ordering of mathematical knowledge that was at once inclusive and hierarchical. The historian of mathemat­ics David Rowe was surely right when he treated Klein’s great, collective project—the Encyklopadie der mathematischen Wissenschaften—as a reveal­ing expression of Klein’s conception of mathematical knowledge and its proper organization.24

Klein’s tireless organizational activities have been subject to detailed anal­ysis by, for example, Manegold, Pyenson, Rowe, Schubring, and Tobies.25 The main outlines of the story, as it bears on Gottingen aerodynamics, can be quickly sketched. After his visit, as a representative of the Prussian govern­ment, to the World’s Fair in Chicago in 1893, Klein became convinced of the need for German universities to attach more importance to applied science and technology. By 1897 he had been able to persuade the government and the University of Gottingen to create an institute for applied physics. In 1898 Klein and Henry von Bottinger, the vigorous and persuasive chairman of the Bayer chemical company, founded the Gottinger Vereinigung zur Forderung der angewandten Physik und Mathematik. This was a novel institutional ve­hicle by which commercial firms could finance applied research in the uni­versity.26 On this basis, in 1905, the original Institute for Applied Physics grew into the Institute for Applied Mathematics and Mechanics under Prandtl and Runge.27

When Klein was pressing the authorities to appoint Prandtl, he was ex­plicit about the engineering connection.28 He introduced Prandtl as someone “who combines the expert knowledge of the engineer with a mastery of the apparatus of mathematics and has a strong power of intuition combined with a great originality of thought” (“der mit der Sachkenntnis des Ingenieurs und der Beherrschung des mathematischen Apparatus eine starke Kraft der Intuition und eine grofie Originalitat des Denkens verbindet”; 232). It was Klein who prompted Prandtl to bring problems connected with airships and aerodynamics within the scope of his new institute.29 The Motorluftschiff – Studiengesellschaft, the Society for the Study of Motorized Airships, which had been founded in July 1906, provided the finance for setting up a model­testing facility at Gottingen, the Modellversuchsanstalt, with its wind channel designed by Prandtl and constructed by Fuhrmann. The channel was given a test run in December 1908 and went into operation in January 1910. In Octo­ber 1913 the model-testing facility was taken over by the university.30

There is no doubt that Prandtl was in close contact with all the leading mathematicians and physicists at Gottingen. He went with them on their af­ternoon walks; he plotted with them over local academic politics; he sat at the “high table” along with Klein and Hilbert during the intimidating meetings of the Gottingen Mathematical Society.31 He was a friend and neighbor of Karl Schwarzschild, who was at work solving the field equations of Einstein’s general theory of relativity.32 Unlike that of his colleagues, Prandtl’s intellec­tual life was not dominated by the struggles over the nature of gravity or the structure of matter. His mathematical heritage lay elsewhere, in the technis – che Mechanik of the engineering tradition and August Foppl’s textbooks.33 The significance of this tradition is conveyed with some force by the lengthy account that Runge and Prandtl wrote in 1906 describing the history and work of their Institute for Applied Mathematics and Mechanics.34 It is full of enthusiastic and detailed specifications of pumps, boilers, condensers, dyna­mos, diesels, turbines, and electrically driven ventilators (which were used in the aerodynamic experiments). No wonder their colleagues made sly jokes about the Department of Lubricating Oil.35 This was not the world of the philosopher-mathematician or the physicist-as-cosmologist, any more than it was the world of Horace Lamb, Augustus Love, or Lord Rayleigh. Certainly the Cambridge mathematicians would not have chosen the words with which Runge and Prandtl ended their article:

Die technischen Wissenschaften sind reich an Kapiteln, deren volles Verstand – nis eine tiefe mathematische Bildung erfordert. Der Unterricht setzt sich zum Ziel, die Entwicklung der mathematischen Methoden zu vereinigen mit dem vollen Verstandnis der praktischen Probleme in dem Umfang und in der Fas – sung, wie sie sich dem ausubenden Ingenieur darbieten. (280)

Technical science is rich in material whose full understanding demands a deep mathematical education. The goal of the teaching [at the institute] is to unite the development of mathematical methods and a complete understanding of practical problems in as far as they concern, and in the manner they present themselves to, practicing engineers.

This was neither the voice of Tripos-oriented Cambridge, nor the voice of the mathematical Gottingen that has attracted the lion’s share of the historian’s attention, but it was the voice of Prandtl’s Gottingen. There is no problem in acknowledging this difference as long as it is recognized that the University of Gottingen was not a unified intellectual environment. Of course, there was overlap between its different parts both personally and institutionally: Runge had worked on atomic spectra and von Karman was a friend of Max Born’s and collaborated with him on the quantum theory of specific heats.36 But it was engineering that defined the orientation of the aerodynamic work, and this orientation had an institutional niche in Gottingen thanks to Klein’s efforts.37

Institutional plurality was wholly consistent with Klein’s vision and prac­tice. Mathematics, for Klein, always had an integrating function in science, but that function was to be discharged in diverse ways. It required coordi­nation and cooperation, but it did not require that everyone have the same preoccupations. That would have run counter to the encyclopedic outlook that informed Klein’s organizational plans. Klein had himself lectured on me­chanics at Gottingen and had tried to offset the tendency toward excessive mathematical abstraction. In doing this he had, as von Mises put it, restored “the essential but almost lost connection with ‘technical mechanics.’”38 In 1900 Klein gave a general lecture titled “Ueber technische Mechanik” in which he sought to capture the special qualities of the discipline.39 Like Au­gust Foppl, Klein asserted that practitioners of technical mechanics had their own Fragestellung, that is, their own way of posing and answering questions. It involved subtle judgments and made unique demands. In particular Klein noted the problematic relation between technologically oriented mathemat­ics and the established knowledge of basic physical principles: “Es ist vielfach nicht moglich, die Erscheinungen mit den Principien oder Grundgleichun – gen der classischen Mechanik in luckenlosen Zusammenhang zu bringen” (28) (Very often it is impossible to bring phenomena into a rigorous relation­ship to the principles and fundamental equations of classical mechanics). In the eyes of some of Klein’s technological critics, these sympathetic method­ological insights were not enough. Nor were Klein’s Gottingen seminars on elasticity, graphical statics, and hydrodynamics always deemed a success. The implied commitment to technology, said the critics, was inadequate. This was the line taken by the engineer H. Lorenz, who had been brought to Gottingen by Klein but who had left in disappointment and, in a flurry of anti-Klein criticism, had taken himself off to the TH at Danzig.40 Klein was always fight­ing on two fronts. On the one side were those within the universities who argued that technology was not a fit subject for a truly academic institution, and on the other side were those within the technische Hochschulen who saw technology as the special preserve of these institutions. Both sides resented Klein’s suggestion that the universities involve themselves with applied sci­ence and technology.

Klein’s attempts to meet these conflicting accusations were not always suc­cessful. He eventually got his way, but not without frustrations and compro­mise. He supported the technische Hochschulen in their fight for the right to grant doctoral degrees, but there were delicate issues of status involved. Klein tried to find a division of labor in which different roles were to be played by the different institutions. On one occasion, in 1895, he sought to convey his vision by means of a military metaphor. He spoke of the universities as providing the Generalstabsoffiziere der Technik or “general-staff officers” of technology, while the products of the technical institutions would consti­tute the “frontline officers.”41 Perhaps Klein thought that the heroic image of frontline combat would make the suggestion acceptable to colleagues in the technische Hochschulen. If so, he was wrong. The implied disparities of rank and status were too blatant to ignore.

One of those who took offense was August Foppl. Without naming Klein as the source of the military metaphor, Foppl pointedly remarked that if one were going to speak in these terms, then each different arm of the military service (Waffengattung) should be accorded equal value. Were they not all equal as comrades in arms? The route to the top, and promotion to high command, should depend on the qualities of the individual, not the particu­lar branch of the service in which they happened to be trained.42 But while Foppl bridled at the condescension, his son-in-law was a beneficiary, and exemplification, of Klein’s rank ordering. Prandtl’s institute was devoted to fundamental questions in the field of technology, and he soon occupied a position in which he could influence the strategy of aerodynamic research. Prandtl was indeed a Generalstabsoffizier, and the banner under which his army marched was inscribed with the word “Engineer.”

The point is confirmed by the qualifications of those whom Prandtl re­cruited to serve with him. They prefaced their names with their engineering diplomas and styled themselves Dipl.-Ing. Fuhrmann, Dipl.-Ing Foppl, Dipl.- Ing. Betz, Dipl.-Ing. Wieselsberger, and Dipl.-Ing. Munk.43 Theodore von Karman (fig. 7.4) also had an engineering training and was a graduate of the Royal Technical University of Budapest. He had originally come to Gottingen to do research with Prandtl on elasticity and the strength of materials but, as he was fond of recounting, turned to hydrodynamics through reflecting theoretically on the experimental difficulties of his colleague Karl Hiemenz.44 This was the origin of von Karman’s work on the stability of vortex motion and his mathematical analysis of the shedding of vortices that formed a flow pattern called a Karman vortex street.45 A number of Prandtl’s inner circle

Klein and the General-Staff Officers

figure 7.4. Theodore von Karman (1881-1963). Von Karman trained as an engineer in Hungary and then worked with Prandtl in Gottingen. Later he moved to the technische Hochschule in Aachen and built up a rival institute of aeronautics and fluid dynamics. (By permission of the Royal Aeronautical Society Library)

eventually left Gottingen to take up positions in the technische Hochschulen. Foppl, Wieselsberger, and von Karman all went to Aachen, making it a pow­erful rival to Gottingen. Aachen was not Gottingen, but von Karman was not a humble man.46 Without doubt, he and his colleagues still saw themselves as ranking members of the general staff of aeronautical technology.

Evanescent Viscosity

Glauert’s contribution to the London Congress was a paper titled “Some As­pects of Modern Aerofoil Theory.”96 It covered much of the same ground as the methodological paper given to the RAeS, but with the addition of tech­nical results about propeller theory and wind-tunnel corrections. Though deeply opposed to Bairstow’s view, Glauert did not directly attack what had just been said. Instead he quietly sought to outflank it by demonstrating that the concern with “fundamentals,” as Bairstow conceived it, was out of touch with events at the front line of active research.

Glauert began by pointing out that the study of the forces and moments on a body in motion through a viscous fluid was beset by complexity and prog­ress had been slow. But a “modified form of the classical hydrodynamics” was proving successful. “The present paper,” Glauert went on, “is concerned only with the problem of aerofoil structures, whose essential characteristic is that they give a relatively large lift force at right angles to the direction of motion at the expense of a relatively small drag force retarding the motion” (245). A few minutes earlier Bairstow had drawn attention to the “limited” scope of application of the circulatory theory as a point of criticism and as an unac­ceptable feature of the work of Kutta, Joukowsky, and Prandtl. Right at the outset of his talk Glauert was doing the opposite. He was drawing attention to the limited focus of the work as a wholly-taken-for-granted feature that in no way told against it. Glauert was implicitly making an engineering-style response to Bairstow of exactly the kind that Lanchester had made, explicitly, in the 1915 confrontation.

Having led his audience, nonmathematically, through the main develop­ments in aerofoil theory, Glauert concluded by saying that the most impor­tant feature of the “modern” approach was that it “presents us with a point of view” with which to examine new problems. It provides us with a small number of theoretical conceptions “which serve to bind into a single unity a multitude of experimental results” (255). Clearly this point of view was dif­ferent from that adopted by Bairstow—and Glauert’s idea of unity was not Bairstow’s. For Bairstow unity meant deducibility from the Stokes equations; for Glauert it meant linking experimental results by adopting the modern, methodological standpoint. Glauert expressed himself in an interesting way. Referring to the moment when the boundary layer became infinitely thin, he said, “The effect of the evanescent viscosity is represented in the non-viscous solution by the possibility of a circulation round the aerofoil” (246).

The word “evanescent” means “passing quickly from sight or memory.” It was also the old Newtonian word for describing the infinitesimal quanti­ties that entered into the differential calculus. Infinitesimals were “evanescent quantities” that were neither zero nor nonzero but poised on the very brink of vanishing. Newton and his followers spoke in this way because they did not possess the modern concept of a limiting process.97 Glauert, of course, did possess it. His idea was to contrast the limiting value of, say, /(p) as p ^ 0 with the value of /(0) , that is, the value of the function at p = 0. These can be different. Glauert’s “evanescent viscosity” was thus viscosity on the point of reaching the limit zero, but his language was meant to register a method­ological as well as a mathematical point. It signalizes the difference between deciding that viscosity is zero in step 1 of his three-step methodology, and accepting that it may be treated as zero in step 3.

Bairstow wanted to know why ideal-fluid theory sometimes worked. Glauert’s answer was that it works when the ideal flow is a limiting case of a flow that would take place in a fluid of small viscosity. This answer was not one that Bairstow was prepared to accept. Recall that Bairstow saw no “im­passable barrier” to the idea of a boundary layer, but, he said, difficulties be­gan when the region was said to have an infinitesimal width (244). Bairstow did not want the relationship between inviscid and viscous flows to hinge on a limiting process, and certainly not on a limiting process that was carried out informally. He did not want Glauert’s “evanescent” viscosity; he wanted what, in his own mind, would count as physically real viscosity.98

Pessimism, Positivism, and Relativism:. Aerodynamic Knowledge in Context

Menschen haben geurteilt, ein Konig konne Regen machen; wir sagen dies widersprache aller Erfahrung. Heute urteilt man, Aeroplan, Radio, etc. seien Mittel zur Annaherung der Volker und Ausbreiting von Kultur.

Men have judged that a king can make rain; we say this contradicts all experience. Today they judge that aeroplanes and the radio etc. are means for the closer contact of peoples and the spread of culture.

ludwig Wittgenstein, Uber Gewifiheit, On Certainty (1969)1

The British resistance to the circulatory theory of lift casts light on a number of wider themes, some methodological, some cultural, and some philosophi­cal. Here I take the opportunity afforded by the case study to pose and answer some of the questions of this kind that have been raised. The first thing is to make explicit the methodological principles that have informed my own inquiry. The present study is not only an exercise in the history of science and technology; it is also a contribution to the sociology of knowledge. My approach has been that of the Strong Program in the sociology of knowl­edge, and so I start this chapter with a brief account and defense of the main features of the program and the perspective it is designed to encourage. It is a perspective very different from the naive, philosophical narratives I identi­fied at the end of the last chapter and that I mentioned in the introduction.2 I then address two broader questions. First, was the resistance to the circula­tory theory of lift an all-too-typical example of British failings in the field of technological innovation? I argue against this pessimistic reading. Second, what about the controversial topic of “relativism”? Aviation, as a successful and impressive technology, is often cited as a quick and decisive refutation of relativism. I believe this line of antirelativist argument is groundless and obscures the most striking characteristics of aerodynamic knowledge.

In this chapter I make use of the writings of the Viennese physicist Philipp Frank. Frank was a specialist in modern physics, but he wrote some half dozen papers on fluid dynamics and aeronautical topics.3 He knew many of the leading experts in these fields and was a lifelong friend of Richard von Mises. Frank is relevant to my discussion for two reasons. First, he compared the

way a scientific theory is assessed to the way the performance of an aircraft is assessed. I follow Frank in this aeronautical comparison and then close the circle by applying his comparison directly to theories in aerodynamics. Sec­ond, Frank’s work provides a valuable resource when discussing relativism. I use Frank’s simple and forthright definition of the word “relativism” to struc­ture my own discussion.

The Euler Equations

The second principle states that fluid elements obey Newton’s second law of motion, F = MX A, that is, force equals mass times acceleration. Figure 2.2 is a picture of a fluid element whose sides are parallel with the x – and y-axes. As in the previous discussion, the flow is assumed to be “two-dimensional,” so the z-axis plays no role in the analysis. The element is again assumed to be of unit depth and can be represented by a rectangle ABCD (whose “depth” bz = 1). Thus the mass of a small, rectangular fluid element with sides bx and by is pbxby. In aerodynamics the effect on the air of external forces, such as gravity, can be neglected. The resultant force on the fluid element in the x-direction comes from difference between the pressures on the two faces AD

The Euler Equations

figure 2.2. Small fluid element showing pressure on the faces AD and BC. The pressure difference is the force producing the acceleration along the x-axis. From Cowley and Levy 1918, 37.

and BC. Let the pressure on AD be p. The pressure on BC is then p+d-Sx,

dx

that is, the original pressure plus the change in pressure over the length of the element. The resultant thrust on the element is

pSy—| p+dp Sx lay=—dp Sx8y.

dx ) dx

This is the force causing the acceleration. Newton’s second law then takes the form

What is the acceleration in the x-direction? The desired term is du/dt, the rate of change of the velocity u with time t. The velocity u is a function of three variables: x, y, and t. The acceleration is given by a process of differentiation involving all three variables which is called “differentiation following the mo­tion of the fluid.”16 Thus,

du du dx + du dy + du dt dt dx dt dy dt dt dt

du dx + du dy + du dx dt dy dt dt

This expression can be simplified. If the restriction is introduced that the flow is steady, then d. = 0. Also, by definition, – А = u and – А = v. Substituting these terms in the expression for Newton’s law yields

dp I du du |

— = 4 U + V ) •

Similar reasoning gives the equation for the y-direction:

dp I dv dv

-ay=plu dX+v dy

These are the Euler equations for the two-dimensional steady flow of an ideal fluid. A mathematician will identify them as nonlinear, partial differen­tial equations that relate the pressure p and the velocity components u and v. Along with the equation of continuity they constitute the fundamental equa­tions of motion of an ideal fluid. They completely determine the motion. The integration, or solution, of the equations will, however, involve arbitrary functions and constants, and these require knowledge of (1) the initial condi­tions of the motion and (2) the position of any fixed boundaries. These two specifications are called the boundary conditions.

An Old Anomaly or a New Crisis?

How did the leading British aerodynamicists react? The theory of lift derived from the picture of discontinuous flow could not be right, at least, not as it stood. Was this situation to be treated (in Kuhn’s terms) as a “crisis”? Did it call for a radical response involving the use of new models and the creation of a wholly new approach to lift? Or was it no more than an “anomaly”? Was there still the possibility that some refinement of the old, discontinuity ap­proach would eventually allow the problem to be met? The answer is that the problem was seen as both an anomaly and a crisis, but it was seen in these different ways by different groups. The split was roughly along disciplinary lines. For the more purely mathematical contributors, the emerging results represented, or were collectively treated, as an anomaly rather than a crisis; for the experimentalists and physicists, even the mathematical physicists, the findings were more than merely anomalous: they were taken to herald a full­blown crisis.34

Greenhill, Bryan, and a number of other research mathematicians con­tinued to work on the problems of discontinuous flow. They aimed to refine the analysis by taking account of the curvature that was characteristic of the cross section of a wing. This involved complicating the Schwarz-Christoffel transformation, which applied to straight-sided figures. In 1914 G. H. Bryan and Robert Jones published a paper called “Discontinuous Fluid Motion Past a Bent Plane, with Special Reference to Aeroplane Problems.”35 They were able to align the analysis with some of the qualitative facts, for example, that a moderate degree of camber can increase lift without increasing drag. In 1915 J. G. Leathem (the sixth wrangler in 1894 and a fellow of St. John’s) published “Some Applications of Conformal Transformations to Problems of Hydrodynamics,” which was meant to put the introduction of “curve – factors” on a systematic basis.36 Also in 1915, Hyman Levy published “On the Resistance Experienced by a Body Moving in a Fluid,” in which he set out to link a discontinuity analysis to recent work on vortices by von Karman.37 In 1916 Greenhill published a substantial appendix to his R&M 19 which was titled “Theory of a Stream Line Past a Curved Wing.” Greenhill noted that a curved surface could be approximated by a large number of short, straight surfaces so that the way was open to work with a more realistic model of a wing. He added to his previous discussion by surveying the contributions to discontinuity theory of French and Italian mathematicians such as Bril – louin, Villat, Cissotti, and Levi-Civita.38 The same year, 1916, saw Levy’s “Dis­continuous Fluid Motion Past a Curved Boundary.”39 The investigation was again justified by its relevance to aerodynamics. The author asserted that “In aeronautics alone recent developments have shown the practical necessity for an effective discussion of the case where the plane is cambered” (285).

What kept the mathematicians at work?40 Partly, they hoped to bring dis­continuity theory into closer contact with experimental results, as indeed they did; it would be wrong, however, to overstate the optimism associated with this project. The main factor seems to have been the lack of any per­ceived alternative. The question they faced was whether there was any chance of digging beneath the equations of perfect fluid theory and making progress with the full, governing equations of viscous flow. If there was no chance, or very little chance, then it was reasonable to carry on as before. Consider the stance of Cowley and Levy. They concluded that the fatal flaw in the theory of discontinuous flow was that it depended on the assumptions of the theory of a perfect fluid, although, they argued, “it is remarkable. . . that the results ob­tained for the resistance are comparable at all with those derived from experi­ment” (65), and they speculated that perfect fluid flows with vortices might be used to simulate the flows that could be photographed in a turbulent, viscous fluid.41

While Cowley and Levy spoke of the mathematics of viscous flow as “not yet sufficiently developed” (75)—thus holding out hope—a more pessimistic induction is hinted at by G. H. Bryan’s remarks in the Mathematical Gazette of 1912.42 With a nod to Greenhill’s article on hydrodynamics in the Encyclo­paedia Britannica, Bryan said that the subject really consists in the study of certain partial differential equations and not “town water supply, resistance of ships, screw propellers and aeroplanes” (379). There was not much induce­ment for the mathematician to adapt his work to the needs of engineers. If he were going to do that, he might as well become an engineer “and give up most of his mathematics, relying on the introduction of constants or coefficients to save him from running his head against insoluble differential equations” (379). As for the hypothetical conditions that make hydrodynamics so unreal, these have “pretty well done their duty when they have been made use of to write down differential equations” (379). So it was not the empirical status of these conditions (that is, their falsity) that counted, but their power to help the mathematician frame tractable equations. The real issue was “remarkably simple”: if you give up ideal fluid theory, you get equations for which nobody can find the integrals, “at least, mathematicians have tried over and over in vain to find them” (379). And the same argument applied to the simplifying assumption of steady motion, which involved, and justified, ignoring “for example, eddy formation in the rear of planes” (380). Bryan’s position was the same as the one he adopted in his main field of research into stability. There the equations turned out to be accurate, but for Bryan, this was a bo­nus rather than something that was necessary for justifying the work. Even if inaccurate, he said, the analysis might still furnish a useful basis for the interpretation of experimental data.

Such was the reasoning by which a small number of high-status math­ematicians justified their continued elaboration of discontinuity theory and sustained a pessimistic form of “normal science.” For Bairstow, and others at

the NPL who were more experimentally inclined, the emerging problems in­dicated the end of the road for discontinuity theory. The theory was artificial and doomed to failure because it was grounded in the unreal conception of a perfect, frictionless fluid. What was needed was a return to the full equations of viscous flow and the attempt to develop new methods of approximation. For the moment, however, Bairstow accepted that the complex flow around a wing was beyond the comprehension of the mathematician.

In a lecture at the Aeronautical Society, on February 12, 1913, Bairstow asked what shape of aerofoil or strut would give the most lift or the least resistance.43 “A true theory of aerodynamics,” he said, “would answer these questions for us completely, but unfortunately for us the answers to such questions are beyond the reach of our present mathematical knowledge.” To reinforce the point Bairstow showed his audience a photograph that, he said, “illustrates a motion which has defied the mathematician” (117). The photo­graph was one of the NPL water-channel pictures showing a wing with the characteristic turbulent wake associated with a stall, that is, a wing exhibiting Kirchhoff-Rayleigh flow. Greenhill was in the audience—but he did not de­fend his mathematical model of discontinuous flow around a wing, nor did he challenge Bairstow’s conclusion. It is difficult to know how to interpret this disregard. Greenhill initiated the discussion that followed the lecture, but only to make jocular comments on the law of mechanical similarity. Ac­cording to Greenhill’s calculations, if angels existed in the form in which they are usually depicted, then they would have to be about the size of a bee.44 This lack of an explicit response to the shortcomings of the discontinuity theory was wholly characteristic. There had been no discussion of the de­mise of discontinuity theory at the meetings of the Advisory Committee (or none at which minutes were taken). Greenhill, though in regular attendance, appears to have made few contributions to the business of the committee. Anecdotal evidence reveals that Sir George was actually prone to fall asleep during meetings. On one such occasion Mervin O’Gorman, a talented artist, drew a sketch of the slumbering mathematician and left it on the table. The caption was from the well-known hymn: “There is a green hill far away.”45 But sleep patterns are not really very illuminating. Perhaps the reason for the reticence was simply that Greenhill, and his fellow wranglers on the commit­tee, shared something of Bryan’s pessimism. Without an analysis of viscous flow, the choice was between inviscid theory and empiricism—and inviscid theory had failed.

Bairstow’s slightly more optimistic view, that progress of some kind was possible with the equations of viscous flow, was shared by Geoffrey Ingram Taylor. Taylor came up to Trinity in 1905, took part I of the Mathematical

Tripos in 1907 and part II of the Natural Sciences Tripos in 1908. He was given a major scholarship at Trinity and in 1910 was elected to a fellowship. After war was declared on August 4, 1914, Taylor hurried to submit his dis­sertation for the Adams Prize, unsure whether it would be awarded because of the uncertainty of the international situation. He volunteered his services to the military on August 5, hoping to work in meteorology, but was immedi­ately drafted to Farnborough and later co-opted onto the Aerodynamics Sub­Committee of the ACA. Soon after his arrival at Farnborough, Taylor took his first flight. He flew with Edward Busk, on the day before Busk’s death. Later, after gaining his “wings” with the Royal Flying Corps, Taylor carried out numerous pieces of research, including measurements of the pressure distribution across the wing of a BE2. His work enabled comparisons to be made between wind-channel results on models and full scale data.46 In the early months of the war, however, he used every spare moment to bring his thesis to completion. It was titled “Turbulent Motion in Fluids.”47

The preface and introduction of the thesis were used to set out the current situation in fluid dynamics. Taylor’s position contrasted starkly with that of Bryan, who placed the emphasis on getting hold of some differential equa­tions rather than worrying about what had to be assumed or discarded en route. In Taylor’s view: “In no other branch of applied mathematics is the danger of neglecting the physical basis of the subject greater than it is in hy­drodynamics” (5). It has been possible, he said, to get “rigorous mathemati­cal solutions” in hydrodynamics, but they have no relation to what is found experimentally. Unfortunately, mathematicians adhere to these physically unrealistic assumptions simply because it makes the mathematics easier. As an example Taylor cited the theory of discontinuous flow. The theory is based on the assumption that the pressure in the dead-water region is the same as that of the undisturbed flow, when measurements show it is less than this. Referring to measurements made by Melvill Jones at the NPL, Taylor drew an unequivocal conclusion: “This, I think, finally disposes of the discontinuity theory, which . . . must now be placed among the curiosities of mathematics” (4). The rigor of the old methods, argued Taylor, was well worth sacrificing if there was a chance of explaining the turbulent behavior of real fluids—and this is what he set out to do in the remaining sections of the bulky thesis.48 His aim was to develop a new (statistical) theory of turbulence.

For Taylor, like Bairstow, discontinuity theory and Rayleigh flow were things of the past. The same judgment can be read into what was said, and what was not said, in an important lecture given by Glazebrook in June 1914. His title was “The Development of the Aeroplane,” and the aim was to de­scribe the achievements of the National Physical Laboratory. He mentioned the work of Stanton and Bairstow and explained how pressure measurements reveal the important role of the upper surface of the wing (from the outset, the weak point of the discontinuity theory). Glazebrook mentioned no names and did not make it explicit that the one candidate for the explanation of lift that had been taken seriously in British aerodynamics was now being quietly abandoned. All the attention was directed toward the successful work on sta­bility. The occasion of Glazebrook’s assessment was the second of the Wright Memorial Lectures. It was an important event so the assessment would have been carefully considered.49 The unspoken message was that, notwithstand­ing the opinion of a few of the older mathematicians, the discontinuity theory of lift was dead.