The Politics of Decisions 5. Effacing Difference
Earlier I made an assumption about the overlaps between difference 156 Decisions narratives or performances. I assumed that the various ‘‘options’’ per-
Decisions |
Ex. 7.1 |
Ex. 7.2 |
Ex. 7.3 |
Ex. 7.4 |
Ex. 7.5 |
Cancel outright |
3 |
3 |
3 |
3 |
|
Cancel and order F111A Cancel and take option on F111A Cancel and order F111A and Phantom |
3 |
3 |
3 |
3 |
3 |
Cancel and order a British aircraft |
3 |
3 |
|||
Make no decision until strategic review Continue with TSR2 |
3 |
3 |
3 |
3 |
formed in the early exhibits may be mapped onto one another, that they are indeed sufficiently similar that their differences may be ignored. But now I want to ask whether this is right. And then I want to pose a much more interesting question that follows from this: If we ignore or, alternatively, attend to the differences between the narratives, then what exactly are we doing? This matter takes us to a theme that has recurred in a number of guises: to the politics of difference and their relationship to similarity.21
Table 7.1 performs a similarity by displaying the various options performed by the cabinet in the period March to April 1965 — exhibits 7.1 to 7.5. I shall inquire into the basis of the similarity performed by the table shortly, into what is being done or effaced, in making this list. But first I want to look at the differences that it performs—differ – ences that I earlier more or less elided.
Perhaps there are two ways of treating the divergence between that earlier listing and this table. One is as a question of method. We might argue that the shorter listing was flawed because it ran together important differences between options. Or, as against this, we might argue that the table is unnecessarily fussy. For instance we might insist that some of the distinctions that it draws rest on an unduly literal reading of the various exhibits. Thus we might say that Crossman’s description (exhibit 7.1) of Healey’s position on the F111A is really consistent with that of taking an option on the F111A—and if this is the case then we can collapse these two options together.
The fact is that there is no right answer: any possibility is defeasible in principle.22 Nevertheless, the disagreement maybe understood in two broad ways. On the one hand, we may imagine trying to create a better narrative, one that more closely accords with the events as Decisions 157
these actually took place. In this case we treat it, so to speak, as an issue of method or epistemology, which is what I have been doing in the preceding paragraph. On the other, we may ask what would happen if we abandoned the idea that the exhibits describe a single set of options and instead stick with the idea that they are performing different distributions.
The first approach distinguishes between realities and representations, so it treats the various exhibits, in the way I described earlier, as perspectives: perspectives on a particular event or process, the cabinet meeting that examined the options, or the options themselves, distributions as they actually were. Historians work in this way daily, and so do detectives, journalists, sociologists, and students of technoscience. We all do so, for different perspectives are to be expected. But why would there be different perspectives? A number of responses suggest themselves—and are commonly deployed:
1. People may forget what happened—for instance, that it was an option on the F111A that was being sought by the government rather than an outright purchase.
2. They may perform differences as unimportant or irrelevant— again the difference between option and purchase. This would fit with a theory of social interests, one which says that knowledge is shaped by social concerns. Looked at in this way some matters, some differences, are simply uninteresting from a given standpoint.
3. They may not know fully what was going, being located, for instance, in the public domain rather than in the domain of confidentiality. Perhaps Healey’s biographers are in this position.
4. They may deliberately obscure the facts. Exhibit 7.5, the press release, certainly does not say everything that it might have said about the background for cancellation. (Such an explanation would again be consistent with an account in terms of social interests.)
5. And finally, circumstances change so what appears to be contradiction may simply represent change. Indeed the difference between exhibit 7.9 on the one hand and exhibits 7.1 and 7.2 on the other may be understood in this way (exhibit 7.9 dates from January 17,1965 and the others from April 1).
These moves explain difference by assuming that behind difference there is in fact a unity—for instance, in the form of a single cabinet meeting, a single set of options, a single distribution. They assume and perform the perspectivalism discussed earlier; that is, they assume that more or less adequate perspectives can be obtained on events and objects that are out there and independent of their descriptions. We are thus in the realm of epistemology and of method. We are in the business of assessing which description or combination of descriptions is most satisfactory and is most likely to accord with what really went on.
All of this is standard in the social sciences, not to mention life. But now we might note this: these perspectival, methodological, or epistemological moves would work equally well precisely to conceal lack of unity, to conceal the possibility that there is difference (as one might say) all the way down—and to efface the prospect that there is nothing out there that is independent of the methods through which it is described. Which, to be sure, makes the move toward ontology and performativity developed in chapter 2—while explaining why it is that matters appear to have to do with epistemology, perspective, and method.
In this way of thinking the world, the worlds, are being made in interference between performances and narratives. They are being made, in part, in coordinations or resonances between performances and narratives. And this is what we have witnessed here—for similar distributions make themselves through the various exhibits that I have discussed. Listing, generating discretion, distinguishing between reality and fantasy, effacing that which is turned into ‘‘detail,’’ and then effacing the fact that there is effacing—all of these are performed in the more specific narratives and allocations of the cancellation decision. And the differences between these narratives, real though they are, tend to distract attention from their commonalities: from their tendency to enact similar ontological work—that of making a discretionary center.
But there is something more to be said. The hypothesis would be that places of discretion, decision-making centers, exist because, in the kind of oscillatory motion I have explored in earlier chapters, they are able to enact a distribution between the performance of narra-
tive coherence and simplicity on the one hand and noncoherence and multiplicity on the other. This argument comes in two parts. First, such centers (appear to) make firm decisions because they (appear to) draw things together in a coherent manner—and indeed they do so, because that is what any particular performance enacts. Richard Crossman is clear enough about the options and so too is Harold Wilson, which suggests that firm decisions are indeed being made. It is just that their lists do not coincide. But this is the second point— they are able to make firm decisions at all because they are, indeed, performing many different decisions. All at the same time, and in parallel, decisions that are then coordinated and performed as if they were the same, as if they were a singularity.23
I am being cautious. I am not saying that what is being coordinated—all these different decisions or lists of options—is incoherent. To say so would be to make a move within the distributions of centered decision making. Rather I am saying that it is noncoherent, that it is complex, and that part of the politics of centered decision making rests on this by now familiar double trick of managing the simultaneous performance of singularity and multiplicity, of, so to speak, being singular while performing multiplicity, or (it works equally well the other way round) of being multiple while performing singularity. So I am suggesting that here there is a kind of double play, a double looseness, another form of heterogeneity, another version of absence/presence, the simultaneous performance of solidity and fluidity.24 At any rate, the possibility of ‘‘decision making’’ and, indeed, of High Politics rests in an interference, an overlap, where the performance of similarity depends on difference, and the performance of difference depends on the enactment of similarity.
Such, then, is one strategy of coordination or (it amounts to the same thing) one mode of interference. An interference that makes a fractional object, a decision, that is more than one but less than many.